other theory, making due allowances for its Socratic aspects (§9). There is
no reason to suppose that its first principles or assumptions need to be
self-evident, or that its concepts and criteria can be replaced by other
notions which can be certified as non-moral.
34
Thus while I have main-
tained, for example, that something’s being right, or just, can be under-
stood as its being in accordance with the relevant principles that would be
acknowledged in the original position, and that we can in this way replace
the former notions by the latter, these definitions are set up within the
theory itself (§18). I do not hold that the conception of the original
position is itself without moral force, or that the family of concepts it
draws upon is ethically neutral (§23). This question I simply leave aside.
I have not proceeded then as if first principles, or conditions thereon, or
definitions either, have special features that permit them a peculiar place
in justifying a moral doctrine. They are central elements and devices of
theory, but justification rests upon the entire conception and how it fits in
with and organizes our considered judgments in reflective equilibrium. As
we have noted before, justification is a matter of the mutual support of
many considerations, of everything fitting together into one coherent
view (§4). Accepting this idea allows us to leave questions of meaning
and definition aside and to get on with the task of developing a substan-
tive theory of justice.
The three parts of the exposition of this theory are intended to make a
unified whole by supporting one another in roughly the following way.
The first part presents the essentials of the theoretical structure, and the
principles of justice are argued for on the basis of reasonable stipulations
concerning the choice of such conceptions. I urged the naturalness of
these conditions and presented reasons why they are accepted, but it was
not claimed that they are self-evident, or required by the analysis of moral
concepts or the meaning of ethical terms. In the second part I examined
the sorts of institutions that justice enjoins and the kinds of duties and
obligations it imposes on individuals. The aim throughout was to show
that the theory proposed matches the fixed points of our considered con-
victions better than other familiar doctrines, and that it leads us to revise
and extrapolate our judgments in what seem on reflection to be more
satisfactory ways. First principles and particular judgments appear on
34. The view proposed here accords with the account in §9 which follows “Outline for Ethics”
(1951). But it has benefited from the conception of justification found in W. V. Quine,
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: