one knows at this point, that some form of the principle of utility would
be adopted, and therefore that contract theory leads eventually to a deeper
and more roundabout justification of utilitarianism. In fact a derivation of
this kind is sometimes suggested by Bentham and Edgeworth, although it
is not developed by them in any systematic way and to my knowledge it is
not found in Sidgwick.
14
For the present I shall simply assume that the
persons in the original position would reject the utility principle and that
they would adopt instead, for the kinds of reasons previously sketched,
the two principles of justice already mentioned. In any case, from the
standpoint of contract theory one cannot arrive at a principle of social
choice merely by extending the principle of rational prudence to the
system of desires constructed by the impartial spectator. To do this is not
to take seriously the plurality and distinctness of individuals, nor to rec-
ognize as the basis of justice that to which men would consent. Here we
may note a curious anomaly. It is customary to think of utilitarianism as
individualistic, and certainly there are good reasons for this. The utilitari-
ans were strong defenders of liberty and freedom of thought, and they
held that the good of society is constituted by the advantages enjoyed by
individuals. Yet utilitarianism is not individualistic, at least when arrived
at by the more natural course of reflection, in that, by conflating all
systems of desires, it applies to society the principle of choice for one
man. And thus we see that the second contrast is related to the first, since
it is this conflation, and the principle based upon it, which subjects the
rights secured by justice to the calculus of social interests.
The last contrast that I shall mention now is that utilitarianism is a
teleological theory whereas justice as fairness is not. By definition, then,
the latter is a deontological theory, one that either does not specify the
good independently from the right, or does not interpret the right as
maximizing the good. (It should be noted that deontological theories are
defined as non-teleological ones, not as views that characterize the right-
ness of institutions and acts independently from their consequences. All
ethical doctrines worth our attention take consequences into account in
judging rightness. One which did not would simply be irrational, crazy.)
Justice as fairness is a deontological theory in the second way. For if it is
assumed that the persons in the original position would choose a principle
of equal liberty and restrict economic and social inequalities to those in
14. For Bentham see
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: